Identity and the Cognitive Value of Logical Equations in Frege’s Foundational Project

Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 64 (4):495-544 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In this article, I first analyze and assess the epistemological and semantic status of canonical value-range equations in the formal language of Frege’s Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. I subsequently scrutinize the relation between (a) his informal, metalinguistic stipulation in Grundgesetze I, Section 3, and (b) its formal counterpart, which is Basic Law V. One point I argue for is that the stipulation in Section 3 was designed not only to fix the references of value-range names, but that it was probably also intended to play a regulative role with an eye to Basic Law V. I further intend to shed new light on the status of Frege’s identification of the truth-values with their unit classes in Grundgesetze I, Section 10 and determine its place and importance in his overall logicist project. In a subsequent section, I first discuss the hypothetical extendability of the logical system of Grundgesetze. In what follows, I analyze the incompleteness of that system—were it not inconsistent and hence trivially complete—by focusing on the role of the definite description operator and the axiom governing it (= Basic Law VI) as well as on the role of the application operator. The latter is defined by means of the former. I further comment on the redundancy of an axiom that could be designed to supplement Basic Law VI by incorporating the second clause of Frege’s two-part elucidation of the description operator. I argue that although it seems likely that Basic Law VI could have been shown to be dispensable in Grundgesetze, Frege would probably have been reluctant to dispense with it, despite his commitment to axiomatic parsimony. In my view, the reason is that he considers it essential that every primitive function-name of his formal language be governed and grounded by a basic law that is tailored to the nature and the role of the primitive name occurring at a key point in the law. Toward the end of the article, I propose solutions to two problems with Frege’s use of “=” in the concept-script sentences that result from his definitions involving the replacement of the double stroke of definition with the judgment-stroke. I conclude the article with a summary of the main results that I have achieved.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,471

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

How to Live Without Identity—And Why.Kai F. Wehmeier - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):761 - 777.
Identity between Semantics and Metaphysics.Dušan Dožudić - 2019 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 19 (3):597-610.
Quine on Identity.Jean-Yves Béziau - 2003 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 7 (1-2):1-15.
Quine on identity.Jean -Yves Béziau - 2003 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 7 (1-2):1-15.

Analytics

Added to PP
2024-03-27

Downloads
25 (#638,434)

6 months
25 (#116,868)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Matthias Schirn
Ludwig Maximilians Universität, München

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Logicism and the ontological commitments of arithmetic.Harold T. Hodes - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (3):123-149.
Cardinality and Acceptable Abstraction.Roy T. Cook & Øystein Linnebo - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (1):61-74.
The Limits of Abstraction.Kit Fine - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 122 (3):367-395.
Frege meets dedekind: A neologicist treatment of real analysis.Stewart Shapiro - 2000 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 41 (4):335--364.
Bad company tamed.Øystein Linnebo - 2009 - Synthese 170 (3):371 - 391.

View all 55 references / Add more references