Is Hegel a Retributivist?

Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 25 (1-2):113-126 (2004)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Amongst contemporary theorists, the most widespread interpretation of Hegel's theory of punishment is that it is a retributivist theory of annulment, where punishments cancel the performance of crimes. The theory is retributivist insofar as the criminal punished must be demonstrated to be deserving of a punishment that is commensurable in value only to the nature of his crime, rather than to any consequentialist considerations. As Antony Duff says: [retributivism] justifies punishment in terms not of its contingently beneficial effects but of its intrinsic justice as a response to crime; the justificatory relationship holds between present punishment and past crime, not between present punishment and future effects. Punishment is given only to persons responsible for committing crime. In addition, the degree of punishment is set in proportion to the relative badness of the precipitating crime. Thus, retributivism can be understood as an individualistic theory because the only relevant factors pertain solely to the individual criminal himself. The general attraction of Hegel's version of retributivism is that the punishments his theory is thought to endorse are commensurable in value with precipitating crimes, in contrast to the strict equivalence required by Kant's theory of punishment. As a result, Hegel's theory is praised both for being more acceptable to modern readers than Kant's so-called ‘pure retributivism’, as well as for being an ‘emphatically anti-utilitarian’ theory. Despite widespread agreement on these general features, it is hotly contested how exactly we are to understand the way in which punishment cancels crimes, and Hegel's difficult style has only served to make the controversy deeper. For example, Ted Honderich says: ‘A punishment is an annulment, a cancellation or a return to a previous state of affairs … All this, of course, is obscure. It is by Hegel’.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,283

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Corlett on Kant, Hegel, and retribution.Thom Brooks - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (4):561-580.
Is Bradley a retributivist?Thom Brooks - 2011 - History of Political Thought 32 (1):83-95.
Hegel’s Retributivist Position on Punishment.Tziporah Kasachkoff - 1976 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 25:192-211.
Making sense of retributivism.J. Angelo Corlett - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (1):77-110.
Retributivism and Fallible Systems of Punishment.George Schedler - 2011 - Criminal Justice Ethics 30 (3):240-266.
Retribution, the Death Penalty, and the Limits of Human Judgment.Anthony P. Roark - 1999 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 13 (1):57-68.
No rubber stamp: Hegel's constitutional monarch.Thom Brooks - 2007 - History of Political Thought 28 (1):91-119.
Hegel: a collection of critical essays.Alasdair C. MacIntyre - 1976 - Notre Dame [Ind.]: University of Notre Dame Press.
Hegel: Philosophy of Politics.Thom Brooks - 2010 - Oxford Bibliographies Online.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-01-18

Downloads
64 (#254,454)

6 months
19 (#138,312)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Thom Brooks
Durham University

References found in this work

Phenomenology of Spirit.G. W. F. Hegel & A. V. Miller - 1977 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (4):268-271.
Science of Logic.M. J. Petry, G. W. F. Hegel, A. V. Miller & J. N. Findlay - 1970 - Philosophical Quarterly 20 (80):273.
Desert.George Sher - 1987 - Princeton University Press.
Phenomenology of Spirit.[author unknown] - 1978 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 40 (4):671-672.

View all 37 references / Add more references