Confused Terms in Ordinary Language

Journal of Logic, Language and Information 29 (2):197-219 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Confused terms appear to signify more than one entity. Carnap maintained that any putative name that is associated with more than one object in a relevant universe of discourse fails to be a genuine name. Although many philosophers have agreed with Carnap, they have not always agreed among themselves about the truth-values of atomic sentences containing such terms. Some hold that such atomic sentences are always false, and others claim they are always truth-valueless. Field maintained that confused terms can still refer, albeit partially, and offered a supervaluational account of their semantic properties on which some atomic sentences with confused terms can be true. After outlining many of the most important theoretical considerations for and against various semantic theories for such terms, we report the results of a study designed to investigate which of these accounts best accords with the truth-value judgments of ordinary language users about sentences containing these terms. We found that naïve participants view confused names as capable of successfully referring to one or more objects. Thus, semantic theories that judge them to involve total reference failure do not comport well with patterns of ordinary usage.

Similar books and articles

Cohen's Criticism of Dummett.D. H. M. Brooks - 1976 - Analysis 36 (3):113 - 117.
A notional worlds approach to confusion.Krista Lawlor - 2007 - Mind and Language 22 (2):150–172.
Semantic Considerations for Sommers’ Logic.George Englebretsen - 1985 - Philosophy Research Archives 11:281-318.
Semantic Considerations for Sommers’ Logic.George Englebretsen - 1985 - Philosophy Research Archives 11:281-318.
Making Metaethics Matter: Can Moral Semantics Improve Moral Inquiry?Christopher Robert Knapp - 2001 - Dissertation, Rutgers the State University of New Jersey - New Brunswick
Truth in Semantics.Max Kölbel - 1981 - In Felicia Ackerman (ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 242–257.
Reference to numbers in natural language.Friederike Moltmann - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 162 (3):499 - 536.
Generic terms and generic sentences.Greg N. Carlson - 1982 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (2):145 - 181.
On Quantifiers and Mass Terms.Gregory Mellema - 1981 - American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (2):165 - 170.
Pejoratives as Fiction.Christopher Hom & Robert May - 2018 - In David Sosa (ed.), Bad Words: Philosophical Perspectives on Slurs. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
An Analysis of Mass Terms and Amount Terms.Terence Parsons - 1970 - Foundations of Language 6 (3):362-388.

Analytics

Added to PP
2019-12-22

Downloads
395 (#51,140)

6 months
102 (#44,152)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

James R. Beebe
University at Buffalo
Greg Frost-Arnold
Hobart and William Smith Colleges

Citations of this work

Coordination, Content, and Conflation.Kyle Landrum - 2023 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 101 (3):638-652.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1947 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.
Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference.Saul Kripke - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):255-276.
Designation.Michael Devitt - 1981 - New York: Columbia University Press.

View all 44 references / Add more references