The Moral Status of Nonresponsible Threats

Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (1):19-32 (2011)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Most people believe that it is permissible to kill a nonresponsible threat, or someone who threatens one's life without exercising agency. Defenders of this view must show that there is a morally relevant difference between nonresponsible threats and innocent bystanders. Some philosophers, including Jonathan Quong and Helen Frowe, have attempted to do this by arguing that one who kills a bystander takes advantage of another person, while one who kills a threat does not. In this paper, I show that the proposals offered by Quong and Frowe have unacceptable implications. I then argue that those who claim that nonresponsible threats may be killed face a dilemma generated by the possibility of a stationary threat, or someone who endangers another person's life without moving. Unless we arbitrarily distinguish between stationary and moving nonresponsible threats, it is unclear how the permission to kill nonresponsible threats is to be explicated. I conclude that nonresponsible threats are not legitimate targets of self-defence

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,197

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Equating innocent threats and bystanders.Helen Frowe - 2008 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (4):277-290.
Conditional Threats.Gerhard Øverland - 2010 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (3):334-345.
A practical account of self-defence.Helen Frowe - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (3):245-272.
Threats, bystanders and obstructors.Helen Frowe - 2008 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 108 (1pt3):365-372.
Consent Under Pressure: The Puzzle of Third Party Coercion.Joseph Millum - 2014 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (1):113-127.
Autonomy under threat: A revised Frankfurtian account.Thomas Nys - 2009 - Philosophical Explorations 12 (1):3 – 17.
Supreme emergencies without the bad guys.Per Sandin - 2009 - Philosophia 37 (1):153-167.
Democratic threats and threats to democracy.Ringo Ossewaarde - 2007 - In Raf Geenens & Annelien de Dijn (eds.), Reading Tocqueville: From Oracle to Actor. Palgrave-Macmillan.
Is the precautionary principle unscientific?B. D. - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 34 (2):329-344.
Why coercion is wrong when it’s wrong.Benjamin Sachs - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (1):63 - 82.
Self-determination, wellbeing, and threats of harm.Antony Lamb - 2008 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (2):145–158.
Self-Defence and the Principle of Non-Combatant Immunity.Helen Frowe - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (4):530-546.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-11-24

Downloads
79 (#212,065)

6 months
5 (#647,370)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Jason Hanna
Northern Illinois University

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references