Phusis, Opposites and Ontological Dependence in Heraclitus

History of Philosophy Quarterly 35 (3):199-217 (2018)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The earliest recorded philosophical use of the term "phusis" occurs in the fragments of Heraclitus (most notably at B1 and B123). Phusis, in the non-philosophical writings relevant to Heraclitus’s time (e.g. from Homer to Aeschylus and Pindar), was generally used to characterize the external physical appearance of something. Heraclitus, on the other hand, seems to have used the term in the completely opposite manner: an object’s phusis is hidden (kruptesthai) and greater (kreissōn) than the external appearance (B123 and B54). Despite this difference, Heraclitus’s use has an affinity with the common use in his time: phusis is used to characterize things. In B1, for example, Heraclitus makes it clear that he is interested in explaining the nature of each thing as opposed to some cosmic principle of Nature. By examining various fragments, I make the case that the phusis of a thing, for Heraclitus, can be defined as the set of opposites necessarily inherent in an object upon which all objects of that kind depend for their existence. The interesting result is that Heraclitus’s novel use of phusis happens to be the foundation for one of the ways in which opposites form a unity. This particular thesis states that there are essential properties inherent in objects which are pairs of opposites sufficient to determine the unity of the object in question. If this is right, then we can read some fragments which contain descriptions of worldly objects (e.g. bows, lyres, rivers, barley drinks etc.) in a new light. These descriptions of worldly objects might not be meant to stand as metaphoric symbols for cosmic principles, as is often thought; rather, they can be read as instances of Heraclitus attempting to do a metaphysics of objects.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,197

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Heraclitus on Religion.Glenn Most - 2013 - Rhizomata 1 (2):153-167.
Heraclitus on Religion.Mantas Adomenas - 1999 - Phronesis 44 (2):87-113.
Heraclitus on religion.Mantas Adome - 1999 - Phronesis 44 (2):2.
Phusis and Nomos in Plato.Zahra Nouri Sanghdehi - 2017 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations at University of Tabriz 11 (20):283-311.
Héraclite et l'unité des opposés.D. O'Brien - 1990 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 95 (2):147–171.
On 'Logos' in Heraclitus.Mark A. Johnstone - 2014 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47:1-29.
On the Concept of the Human Body in Heraclitus.Shawn Loht - forthcoming - Proceedings of the Southeast Philosophy Congress.
Heraclitus, Plato, and the philosophic dogs.Enrique Hülsz Piccone - 2015 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 15:105-115.
Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments. [REVIEW]John Robinson - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (3):497-500.
The Theology of Heraclitus: A Presocratic Pantheism.David John Valiulis - 1980 - Dissertation, University of Toronto (Canada)

Analytics

Added to PP
2018-05-07

Downloads
14 (#993,927)

6 months
11 (#242,683)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Richard Neels
Oklahoma State University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker.Harold Cherniss & Hermann Diels - 1939 - American Journal of Philology 60 (2):248.
On Heraclitus.Gregory Vlastos - 1955 - American Journal of Philology 76 (4):337.
One and many in presocratic philosophy.Michael C. Stokes - 1974 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 164 (1):127-128.

View all 12 references / Add more references