Referential Intentions and Communicative Luck

Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (2):379-384 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Brian Loar [1976] observed that communicative success with singular terms requires more than correct referent assignment. For communicative success to be achieved, the audience must assign the right referent in the right way. Loar, and others since, took this to motivate Fregean accounts of the semantics of singular terms. Ray Buchanan [2014] has recently responded, maintaining that, although Loar is correct to claim that communicative success with singular terms requires more than correct referent assignment, this is compatible with direct reference approaches, as long as one also endorses an independently motivated Gricean view of communicative intentions. This paper argues that Buchanan's Gricean view cannot account for the full range of Loar cases. In doing so, it aims to explicate the structure of Loar's cases and thus to clarify the conditions that a theory must meet in order to adequately meet his challenge.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,197

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Reference, Understanding, and Communication.Ray Buchanan - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (1):55-70.
Brian Loar on singular terms.Michael Devitt - 1980 - Philosophical Studies 37 (3):271 - 280.
What is communicative success?Peter Pagin - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (1):pp. 85-115.
Definite Descriptions Again: Singular Reference, Quantification and Truth-Evaluation.Petr Koťátko - 2009 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 16 (4):552-568.
Reference and propositional attitudes.Brian Loar - 1972 - Philosophical Review 81 (1):43-62.
Communication and indexical reference.Jonas Åkerman - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 149 (3):355 - 366.
A plea for pragmatics.Jonas Åkerman - 2009 - Synthese 170 (1):155 - 167.
Collective Goals and Communicative Action.Raimo Tuomela - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Research 27:29-64.
Kommunikatives Handeln und kooperative Ziele.Raimo Tuomela - 1997 - Analyse & Kritik 19 (2):153-172.
Recognizing communicative intentions in infancy.Gergely Csibra - 2010 - Mind and Language 25 (2):141-168.
Social externalism and the problem of communication.Joey Pollock - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (12):3229-3251.
The role of intersubjectivity for the development of intentional communication.Ingar Brinck - 2008 - In J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha & E. Itkonen (eds.), The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity. John Benjamins. pp. 115--140.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-05-24

Downloads
135 (#137,344)

6 months
20 (#132,313)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Andrew Peet
Umeå University

Citations of this work

Knowledge-yielding communication.Andrew Peet - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (12):3303-3327.
Referential Intentions: A Response to Buchanan and Peet.Elmar Unnsteinsson - 2018 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):610-615.
Frege’s puzzle is about identity after all.Elmar Unnsteinsson - 2019 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 99 (3):628-643.

View all 7 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Epistemic Luck.Duncan Pritchard - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Research 29:191-220.
Utterer’s Meaning and Intentions.H. Paul Grice - 1969 - Philosophical Review 78 (2):147-177.
Epistemic Luck.Duncan Pritchard - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Research 29:191-220.

View all 13 references / Add more references