Consent for Medical Treatment: What is ‘Reasonable’?

Health Care Analysis 32 (1):47-62 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The General Medical Council (GMC) instructs doctors to act ‘reasonably’ in obtaining consent from patients. However, the GMC does not explain what it means to be reasonable: it is left to doctors to figure out the substance of this instruction. The GMC relies on the Supreme Court’s judgment in Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board; and it can be assumed that the judges’ idea of reasonability is adopted. The aim of this paper is to flesh out this idea of reasonability. This idea is commonly personified as the audience that has to be satisfied by the doctor’s justification for offering, or withholding, certain treatments and related information. In case law, this audience shifted from a reasonable doctor to a ‘reasonable person in the patient’s position’; and Montgomery expands the audience to include ‘particular’ patients, too. Senior judges have clarified that the reasonable person is a normative ideal, and not a sociological construct; but they do not set out the characteristics of this ideal. John Rawls has conceived the reasonable person-ideal as one that pursues fair terms of co-operation with other members of society. An alternative ideal can be inferred from the feminist ethic of care. However, the reasonable patient from Montgomery does not align with either theoretical ideal; but, instead, is an entirely rational being. Such a conception conflicts with both real-life constraints on rationality and the doctor’s duty to care for the patient, and it challenges the practice of medicine.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,323

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Mason and McCall Smith's law and medical ethics.J. K. Mason - 2005 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. Edited by G. T. Laurie & Alexander McCall Smith.
Public Health Ethics: The Voices of Practitioners.Ruth Gaare Bernheim - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (s4):104-109.
Public Health Ethics: The Voices of Practitioners.Ruth Gaare Bernheim - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (S4):104-109.
Instructions for Authors.[author unknown] - 2003 - Health Care Analysis 11 (1):93-97.
Instructions for Authors.[author unknown] - 2001 - Health Care Analysis 9 (4):477-482.
Instructions for Authors.[author unknown] - 2001 - Health Care Analysis 9 (1):109-114.
Contents of Volume 8.[author unknown] - 2000 - Health Care Analysis 8 (4):419-421.
Instructions for Authors.[author unknown] - 2003 - Health Care Analysis 11 (4):345-349.
Instructions for Authors.[author unknown] - 2003 - Health Care Analysis 11 (3):269-273.
Reviews. [REVIEW][author unknown] - 1997 - Health Care Analysis 5 (3):244-249.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-08-20

Downloads
12 (#1,090,954)

6 months
8 (#370,917)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

References found in this work

Political Liberalism.J. Rawls - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (3):596-598.
Forced to be free? Increasing patient autonomy by constraining it.Neil Levy - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (5):293-300.
Starting at Home: Caring and Social Policy.Nel Noddings - 2002 - University of California Press.
"The Law of Peoples: With" The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,".John Rawls - 2002 - Philosophy East and West 52 (3):396-396.

View all 15 references / Add more references