How is the culpability we assign to recklessness best accounted for in criminal law?

Dissertation, (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In order to be properly applied, criminal law must determine what conduct warrants punitive action. Figuring out exactly how one must act to be criminally liable is a difficulty that faces any legal system. In many jurisdictions criminal recklessness is regarded as an important notion for liability. However, recklessness is difficult to define, and attempts at this exercise have been a problem in legal philosophy since the mid-twentieth century, and persist today. This thesis discusses accounts of recklessness with the aim of defining it in a way that overcomes several problems which have arisen in recent legal history. It is widely accepted, as well as prima facie intuitive, that people can be culpable for acts committed recklessly. Despite this, whether or not a state of mind is reckless is difficult to define, let alone define in a way that is not only conceptually sound, but also pragmatically apt. Recklessness occurs when an agent engages in some risky activity, but factors like the agent’s attitude and whether the risk is foreseen have been cited as relevant when ascertaining their recklessness. I discuss some difficulties in legally framing recklessness, before criticising some definitional manoeuvres made by judges and scholars in the past. With some problems in previous accounts noted, I consider the foundations of culpability in general. I suggest that two accounts of culpability – the agency theory and the choice theory – are both plausible, and each correlates to a prominent contemporary position on recklessness. After serious consideration of both positions, I conclude that the position advocated by Antony Duff, which I see as in keeping with the agency theory of culpability, is both more generally useful for criminal law and much more coherent with our everyday practices of blaming and punishing.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,283

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Limits of Criminal Culpability.Mark Thornton - 2012 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 25 (1):159-175.
Intoxication and Culpability.Douglas Husak - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3):363-379.
Running risks morally.Brian Weatherson - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 167 (1):141-163.
Concepts of Intention in German Criminal Law.G. Taylor - 2004 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (1):99-127.
Double Effect and the Criminal Law.Alexander Sarch - 2017 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (3):453-479.
Recklessness and the Duty to Take Care.Victor Trados - 2002 - In Stephen Shute & Andrew Simester (eds.), Criminal Law Theory: Doctrines of the General Part. Oxford University Press.
A Non-Aretaic Return to Aristotle.Leo Zaibert - 2011 - Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 97 (2):235-250.
The philosophy of criminal law: selected essays.Douglas N. Husak - 2010 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Towards a Redefinition of the Mens Rea of Rape.Helen Power - 2003 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 23 (3):379-404.
A Theory of Criminal Negligence.Victor Vridar Ramraj - 1998 - Dissertation, University of Toronto (Canada)
The distinction between negligence and recklessness is unstable.Kenneth Simons - 2009 - In Paul Robinson, Kimberly Ferzan & Stephen Garvey (eds.), Criminal Law Conversations. pp. 290--291.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-09-11

Downloads
52 (#308,290)

6 months
8 (#370,373)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Joe Slater
University of Glasgow

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references