Logical analysis and later mohist logic: Some comparative reflections

Comparative Philosophy 1 (1):53-77 (2010)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Any philosophical method that treats the analysis of the meaning of a sentence or expression in terms of a decomposition into a set of conceptually basic constituent parts must do some theoretical work to explain the puzzles of intensionality. This is because intensional phenomena appear to violate the principle of compositionality, and the assumption of compositionality is the principal justification for thinking that an analysis will reveal the real semantical import of a sentence or expression through a method of decomposition. Accordingly, a natural strategy for dealing with intensionality is to argue that it is really just an isolable, aberrant class of linguistic phenomena that poses no general threat to the thesis that meaning is basically compositional. On the other hand, the later Mohists give us good reason to reject this view. What we learn from them is that there may be basic limitations in any analytical technique that presupposes that meaning is perspicuously represented only when it has been fully decomposed into its constituent parts. The purpose of this paper is to (a) explain why the Mohists found the issue of intensionality to be so important in their investigations of language, and (b) defend the view that Mohist insights reveal basic limitations in any technique of analysis that is uncritically applied with a decompositional approach in mind, as are those that are often pursued in the West in the context of more general epistemological and metaphysical programs

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,261

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Mohist canons.Chris Fraser - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Communication and strong compositionality.Peter Pagin - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (3):287-322.
Paradoxes of intensionality.Dustin Tucker & Richmond H. Thomason - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):394-411.
Studies of intensional contexts in mohist writings.Desheng Zong - 2000 - Philosophy East and West 50 (2):208-228.
Jian ai and the Mohist attack of Early Confucianism.Wai Wai Chiu - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (5):425-437.
Are Logical Languages Compositional?Marcus Kracht - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (6):1319-1340.
Pure quotation and general compositionality.Peter Pagin & Dag Westerståhl - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (5):381-415.
Mohist Care.Dan Robins - 2012 - Philosophy East and West 62 (1):60-91.
Logic and Intensionality.Guido Imaguire - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1):111-24.
Intentionality and intensionality.James W. Cornman - 1962 - Philosophical Quarterly 12 (January):44-52.
Compositionality and context.Peter Pagin - 2005 - In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning, and Truth. Oxford University Press. pp. 303-348.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-11-23

Downloads
100 (#174,771)

6 months
14 (#184,493)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Marshall D. Willman
University of Iowa (PhD)

Citations of this work

Mohist canons.Chris Fraser - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Linguistic Problems in the Investigation of Chinese Philosophy.Нanna Hnatovska & Vasyl Havronenko - 2023 - Bulletin of Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv Philosophy 2 (9):13-19.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Principia Ethica.G. E. Moore - 1903 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 13 (3):7-9.
Critique of Pure Reason.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 26 (3):449-451.
Principia Ethica.Evander Bradley McGilvary - 1904 - Philosophical Review 13 (3):351.
Mohist canons.Chris Fraser - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Add more references