Realism and the Riddle of Style

Contemporary Aesthetics 4 (2006)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

My concern in this paper is what, in Art and Illusion, Gombrich calls "the riddle of style". This is the problem of why people at different times and in different cultures have depicted objects in very different ways. An adequate solution to this problem will comprise an explanation of why depiction has a history. The problem seems intractable because of three common assumptions about the history of depiction that, while independently plausible, are inconsistent. First, we assume that this history is a history of realism. Artists from a wide range of cultures and ages seem to have shared the common goal of capturing the visual appearances of the objects they depicted. Secondly, we assume that depictive styles differ from context to context in part because of features internal to the contexts in which they emerged. Finally, we are loathe to accept the claim that differences of style necessarily result from differences in technical capacity. However, these assumptions are in conflict. If artists throughout history sought to capture the appearances of the things they depicted and did not differ markedly in their technical capacities, then surely the pictures each produced should not depend on features internal to the contexts in which they emerged and should instead look more alike. I argue that the history of style is not, in its entirety, a history of realism. Throughout history, pictures have been used to inform viewers about a wide variety of things other than their objects' appearances. Investigating the purposes for which pictures were used in particular historical and cultural contexts will help us to understand why certain styles were appropriate to those contexts. Nevertheless, it will not help us to understand why certain styles were appropriate to just one among a number of contexts in which pictures were used for a single purpose. To understand this, we need to know what cognitive environment was shared by the members of the relevant community. This will enable us to understand why, given the purpose for which pictures were used in that community, a certain style was more informative than another. In addition to cataloguing stylistic changes, therefore, the historian of art has two further tasks: to investigate both the various purposes for which pictures have been used and the cognitive environments of those who used them.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,574

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Pictorial realism.Catharine Abell - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85 (1):1 – 17.
The Very Idea of Perfect Realism.John Andrew Fisher - 1990 - Philosophical Forum 22 (1):49.
Goodman new Riddle is pre-humian+ new-Riddle-of-induction.I. Hacking - 1993 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 47 (185):229-243.
The Riddle of a Riddle.Ivan Gaskell - 2008 - Contemporary Aesthetics 6.
Rabbi Riddle.Leibel Estrin - 2000 - Brooklyn, N.Y.: Shazak Unlimited. Edited by Dovid Sears.
Stil Und Welt.Detlev Lüders - 2011 - Königshausen & Neumann.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-01-17

Downloads
46 (#348,769)

6 months
1 (#1,478,830)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Catharine Abell
University of Oxford

Citations of this work

Depiction.John Hyman & Katerina Bantinaki - 2017 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
The Epistemic Misuse & Abuse of Pictorial Caricature.Christy Mag Uidhir - 2013 - American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (2):137-152.
Art as Alchemy: The Bildobjekt Interpretation of Pictorial Illusion.Jens Dam Ziska - 2018 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76 (2):225-234.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references