The Normative Stance

Philosophical Forum 52 (1):79-89 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The Duhem-Quine thesis famously holds that a single hypothesis cannot be confirmed or disconfirmed in isolation, but instead only in conjunction with other background hypotheses. This article argues that this has important and underappreciated implications for metaethics. Section 1 argues that if one begins metaethics firmly wedded to a naturalistic worldview—due (e.g.) to methodological/epistemic considerations—then normativity will appear to be reducible to a set of social-psycho-semantic behaviors that I call the ‘normative stance.’ Contra Hume and Bedke (2012), I argue that the normative stance provides semantically-grounded entailments from natural truths to normative truths, reducing the latter to the former. Specifically, the normative stance explains the truth-conditions, truth-values, and truth-makers of normative propositions in terms of socially grounded cognitive-behavioral rules and other natural facts, thus explaining how there can be bona fide normative facts and properties in a wholly naturalistic world. I then show that the normative stance explains the apparent stance-independence and non-naturalness of normative reasons, intrinsic value, and categoricity of moral reasons as ‘user-illusions’ generated by people having strong psycho-social propensities—rooted in evolution and social cooperation—to take these normative stances. Section 2 then argues that while the normative stance may appear to naturalists to successfully explain normativity, it will not appeal to those who come to metaethics with different background commitments. I conclude that naturalists should take the normative stance to be a promising metaethical theory of normativity, and that whether it is a true theory of normativity is something that can only be ascertained by determining which background hypotheses—naturalistic or otherwise—we should have when doing metaethics.

Similar books and articles

How to Be a Normative Expressivist.Michael Pendlebury - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (1):182-207.
The Case for Stance Dependent Reasons.David Sobel - 2019 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 15 (2).
Evaluating the Moral Creativity of the Law.Jeffrey Nesteruk - 1999 - Business Ethics Quarterly 9 (4):689-692.
Normative Ethics after Pragmatic Naturalism.Alex Sager - 2014 - Metaphilosophy 45 (3):422-440.
The Normative Stance.Sven Ove Hansson - 2014 - Theoria 80 (2):113-115.
Intentional systems.Daniel C. Dennett - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (February):87-106.
Climate change and normativity: constructivism versus realism.Gideon Calder - 2011 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14 (2):153-169.
Purely Practical Reason: Normative Epistemology from Leibniz to Maimon.Daniel Whistler - 2014 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (2):395-419.
Purely Practical Reason: Normative Epistemology from Leibniz to Maimon.Daniel Whistler - 2013 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (2):395-419.
Naturalism and normative cognition.Matthew S. Bedke - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (1):147-167.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-01-27

Downloads
451 (#43,687)

6 months
116 (#36,002)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Marcus Arvan
University of Tampa

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].
On What Matters: Two-Volume Set.Derek Parfit - 2011 - New York: Oxford University Press.

View all 75 references / Add more references