Moral Intuitionism Defeated?

American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (4):411-422 (2013)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Walter Sinnott-Armstrong has developed and progressively refined an argument against moral intuitionism—the view on which some moral beliefs enjoy non-inferential justification. He has stated his argument in a few different forms, but the basic idea is straightforward. To start with, Sinnott-Armstrong highlights facts relevant to the truth of moral beliefs: such beliefs are sometimes biased, influenced by various irrelevant factors, and often subject to disagreement. Given these facts, Sinnott-Armstrong infers that many moral beliefs are false. What then shall we think of our own moral beliefs? Either we have reason to think some of our moral beliefs are reliably formed or we have no such reason. If the latter, our moral beliefs are unjustified. If we have reason to think some moral beliefs are reliably formed, then those beliefs are not non-inferentially justified, because then we’ll have reason to accept something—namely, that they are reliably formed—that entails or supports those beliefs. But then, either way, our moral beliefs are not non-inferentially justified, and so moral intuitionism is false. This paper takes issue with Sinnott-Armstrong’s interesting and widely discussed argument, which we here call the Empirical Defeat Argument (EDA). According to us, the EDA does not defeat moral intuitionism. In section 1, we will set out the argument, briefly reviewing the rationale Sinnott-Armstrong offers for the premises. Then, in section 2, we identify a critical but dubious epistemological assumption concerning the nature of defeat that undergirds the argument. Finally, in section 3, we will defend our challenge to the EDA by answering two objections.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,682

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Intuitionism.David Kaspar - 2012 - New York: Continuum.
Renewing Moral Intuitionism.Elizabeth Tropman - 2009 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (4):440-463.
Intuitionism and conservatism.Mark T. Nelson - 1990 - Metaphilosophy 21 (3):282-293.
Intuitionism and subjectivism.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - Metaphilosophy 22 (1-2):115-121.
Moderate intuitionism and the epistemology of moral judgment.Robert Audi - 1998 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (1):15-44.
Naturalism and the New Moral Intuitionism.Elizabeth Tropman - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Research 33:163-84.
The Good in the Right. [REVIEW]Vojko Strahovnik - 2005 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 5 (3):583-589.
The New Intuitionism.Jill Graper Hernandez (ed.) - 2012 - London: Continuum.
Non-Inferential Moral Knowledge.Elizabeth Tropman - 2011 - Acta Analytica 26 (4):355-366.
Ethical Intuitionism.Michael Huemer - 2005 - New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Challenges to Audi's ethical intuitionism.Klemens Kappel - 2002 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5 (4):391-413.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-09-29

Downloads
354 (#58,660)

6 months
1 (#1,501,182)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Joshua C. Thurow
University of Texas at San Antonio
Nathan Ballantyne
Arizona State University

References found in this work

Ethical Intuitionism.Michael Huemer - 2005 - New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Moral skepticisms.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Contemporary Theories of Knowledge.John Pollock - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (1):131-140.
The Right and the Good.W. D. Ross - 1930 - Philosophy 6 (22):236-240.

View all 22 references / Add more references