Liberalism in dark times: the liberal ethos in the twentieth century

Princeton: Princeton University Press (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Today, liberals face a predicament: how to defend liberal principles, when adherence to them seems to constitute a fatal disadvantage against unprincipled opponents. The challenge is not new. In the early years of the twentieth century, liberalism was attacked, by critics on both the right and, especially, the left for being hypocritical, naïve, irresponsible, and impotent. It couldn't, for example (anti-liberalists thought), address the acute inequality of imperial rule, racial segregation, and socio-economic poverty. These issues of social justice it was claimed by critics required a politics marked by an uncompromising commitment to ultimate ends, and an unrelenting use of power. Faced with such sentiments and the practical successes of anti-liberal ideologies (i.e. Fascism, Nazism, and Communism) liberals felt pressure to silence their scruples and doubts, and embrace the confidence, ruthlessness, and intransigence exhibited by their opponents. But doing so seemed tantamount to abandoning liberal hopes for, and commitments to, human freedom and all they valued in the first place. In Liberalism for Dark Times, Cherniss tells the story of the liberal response to this challenge in the twentieth century. Through a close study of five leading intellectuals engaged in these debates-Max Weber, Raymond Aron, Albert Camus, Reinhold Niebuhr, and Isaiah Berlin-Cherniss reconstructs a distinctive, neglected strand of liberal thought. This strand defines and defends liberalism as a political ethos: a complex of dispositions, temperament, and sensibility and style-which include skepticism; openness to experience; and careful, discriminating judgment-that shape how individuals make choices, meet challenges, understand and pursue possibilities, and conduct themselves toward others in the course of political struggle. In reconstructing the history of, what he calls, a tempered liberalism, and formulating it as a distinctive political perspective, Cherniss offers an alternative to the prevalent ways of thinking about both, liberalism's history and the intellectual resources available to it today.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,227

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Rise of Danish Agrarian Liberalism.Jeppe Nevers - 2013 - Contributions to the History of Concepts 8 (2):96-105.
Liberalism's Historical Diversity: A Comparative Conceptual Exploration.José María Rosales - 2013 - Contributions to the History of Concepts 8 (2):67-82.
Political Liberalism and Public Reason.Onora O’Neill - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):411-428.
Liberalism and value pluralism.George Crowder - 2002 - New York: Continuum.
Rorty as Virtue Liberal.William M. Curtis - 2016 - Contemporary Pragmatism 13 (4):400-419.
Liberalism's divide, after socialism and before.Jacob T. Levy - 2003 - Social Philosophy and Policy 20 (1):278-297.
Liberalism.H. J. McCloskey - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (187):13-32.
Toward a New Feminist Liberalism.Amy Ruth Baehr - 1997 - Dissertation, State University of New York at Stony Brook
The Origin and Future of Political Liberalism.Kevin Vallier - 2014 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (5):639-656.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-11-30

Downloads
13 (#1,041,239)

6 months
10 (#276,350)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Isaiah Berlin.Joshua Cherniss - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references