Natural Geometry in Descartes and Kepler

Res Philosophica 92 (1):117-148 (2015)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

According to Kepler and Descartes, the geometry of the triangle formed by the two eyes when focused on a single point affords perception of the distance to that point. Kepler characterized the processes involved as associative learning. Descartes described the processes as a “ natural geometry.” Many interpreters have Descartes holding that perceivers calculate the distance to the focal point using angle-side-angle, calculations that are reduced to unnoticed mental habits in adult vision. This article offers a purely psychophysiological interpretation of Descartes’s natural geometry. In his account of perceived limb position from the Treatise on Man, he envisioned a central brain state that controls ocular convergence and thereby co-varies with the distance from observer to object. A psychophysiological law relates the visual perception of distance to this brain state. Descartes also invokes more traditional theories of distance and size perception based on unnoticed judgments, yielding a hybrid account

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,197

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Kepler’s optics without hypotheses.Sven Dupré - 2012 - Synthese 185 (3):501-525.
Kepler's relation to the Jesuits—A study of his correspondence with Paul Guldin.Georg Schuppener - 1997 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 5 (1):236-244.
The development of mersenne's optics.Daniele Cozzoli - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (1):pp. 9-25.
Descartes' Model of Mind.Ray Scott Percival - 2015 - In Robin L. Cautin & Scott O. Lilienfeld (eds.), The Encyclopedia of Clinical Psychology. Wiley-Blackwell.
Fundamental Nature of the Fine-Structure Constant.Michael A. Sherbon - 2014 - International Journal of Physical Research 2 (1):1-9.
Kepler's De quantitatibus.Giovanna Cifoletti - 1986 - Annals of Science 43 (3):213-238.
Descartes' physiology and its relation to his psychology.Gary Hatfield - 1992 - In John Cottingham (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Descartes. Cambridge University Press. pp. 335--370.
Geometry, Time and Force in the Diagrams of Descartes, Galileo, Torricelli and Newton.Emily R. Grosholz - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:237 - 248.
Progress in Mathematics: Descartes' "Geometry".Aaron John Lercher - 1999 - Dissertation, State University of New York at Buffalo
Descartes, la "Géométrie" de 1637.Vincent Jullien - 1996 - Presses Universitaires de France - PUF.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-09-04

Downloads
92 (#187,124)

6 months
6 (#529,161)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Gary Hatfield
University of Pennsylvania

Citations of this work

What Proto-logic Could not be.Woosuk Park - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (6):1451-1482.
Cartesian sensory perception, agreeability, and the puzzle of aesthetic pleasure.Domenica Romagni - 2022 - Tandf: British Journal for the History of Philosophy 30 (3):434-455.
Descartes: new thoughts on the senses.Gary Hatfield - 2017 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (3):443-464.
L’Homme in Psychology and Neuroscience.Gary Hatfield - 2016 - In Stephen Gaukroger & Delphine Antoine-Mahut (eds.), Descartes' Treatise on Man and Its Reception. Springer. pp. 269–285.
Vision, Image, and Imagination in Descartes and Gassendi.Delphine Bellis - 2020 - Les Cahiers Philosophiques de Strasbourg 48:165-192.

Add more citations