Children's Ideas About What Can Really Happen: The Impact of Age and Religious Background

Cognitive Science 45 (10):e13054 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Five‐ to 11‐year‐old U.S. children, from either a religious or secular background, judged whether story events could really happen. There were four different types of stories: magical stories violating ordinary causal regularities; religious stories also violating ordinary causal regularities but via a divine agent; unusual stories not violating ordinary causal regularities but with an improbable event; and realistic stories not violating ordinary causal regularities and with no improbable event. Overall, children were less likely to judge that religious and magical stories could really happen than unusual and realistic stories although religious children were more likely than secular children to judge that religious stories could really happen. Irrespective of background, children frequently invoked causal regularities in justifying their judgments. Thus, in justifying their conclusion that a story could really happen, children often invoked a causal regularity, whereas in justifying their conclusion that a story could not really happen, they often pointed to the violation of causal regularity. Overall, the findings show that children appraise the likelihood of story events actually happening in light of their beliefs about causal regularities. A religious upbringing does not impact the frequency with which children invoke causal regularities in judging what can happen, even if it does impact the type of causal factors that children endorse.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,654

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Aggregating Causal Judgments.Richard Bradley, Franz Dietrich & Christian List - 2014 - Philosophy of Science 81 (4):491-515.
Causal judgment and moral judgment: Two experiments.Joshua Knobe & Ben Fraser - 2008 - In Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Moral Psychology. MIT Press.
Turning Water into Wine.Consuelo Orozco-Giraldo & Paul L. Harris - 2019 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 19 (3-4):219-243.
Philosophy for Children as the Wind of Thinking.Nancy Vansieleghem - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (1):19-35.
Philosophy for children as the wind of thinking.Nancy Vansieleghem - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (1):19–35.
Freedom of religion and children.Hugh LaFollette - 1989 - Public Affairs Quarterly (1):75-87.
Social research in the advancement of children's rights.Sonja Grover - 2003 - Journal of Academic Ethics 1 (1):119-130.
The Importance of Listening to Philosophy that Comes from Children.Sofia Nikolidaki - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 43:95-100.
Questioning Children.Claire Cassidy - 2012 - Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 20 (1-2):62-68.
Checking our sources: the origins of trust in testimony.Paul L. Harris - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (2):315-333.
Books into Ideas.Tim Sprod - 1993 - Camberwell VIC 3124, Australia: ACER.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-10-14

Downloads
17 (#885,561)

6 months
8 (#399,931)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?