Academic Freedom, Feminism and the Probabilistic Conception of Evidence

Philosophy Study 12 (6):22-28 (2022)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

There is a current debate about the extent to which Academic Freedom should be permitted in our universities. On the one hand, we have traditionalists who maintain that Academic Freedom should be unrestricted: people who have the appropriate qualifications and accomplishments should be allowed to develop theories about how the world is, or ought to be, as they see fit. On the other hand, we have post-traditional philosophers who argue against this degree of Academic Freedom. I consider a conservative version of post-traditional philosophy that permits restrictions on Academic Freedom only if the following conditions are met, Condition 1: The dissemination of the results of a given research project R must cause significant harm to some people, especially to people from oppressed groups. Condition 2: Condition 1 must possess strong empirical support, and which accepts the following assumptions: (1) there is a world of objective facts that is, in principle, discoverable, (2) rational means are the means of discovering it and, (3) rational means requires strong empirical support. I define strong empirical support for an hypothesis h on evidence e in probabilistic terms, as a ratio of posterior to prior probabilities substantially exceeding 1. I now argue in favour of a research policy that accepts unrestricted Academic Freedom. My argument is that there is a formal and general quandary that arises within the standard theory of probability when we apply this account of empirical support to a set of possible causal hypotheses framed in such a way that the “reverse probabilities”, pr(e/h) are 1. I consider various possible ways to escape this quandary, none of which are without difficulties, concluding that a research policy allowing for unrestricted Academic Freedom is probably the best that we can hope for.

Similar books and articles

Academic freedom: Its nature, extent and value.Robin Barrow - 2009 - British Journal of Educational Studies 57 (2):178-190.
Ethics, academic freedom and academic tenure.Richard T. De George - 2003 - Journal of Academic Ethics 1 (1):11-25.
Self supporting evidence.Daniel Greco - 2022 - Philosophical Studies 179 (8):2665-2673.
The Evolving Social Purpose of Academic Freedom.Shannon Dea - 2021 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 31 (2):199-222.
New Threats to Academic Freedom.Francesca Minerva - 2013 - Bioethics 28 (4):157-162.
The Genealogy of Judgement: Towards a Deep History of Academic Freedom.Steve Fuller - 2009 - British Journal of Educational Studies 57 (2):164-177.
Academic freedom and academic-industry relationships in biotechnology.Robert Streiffer - 2006 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 16 (2):129-149.
Academic Freedom and the Diminished Subject.Dennis Hayes - 2009 - British Journal of Educational Studies 57 (2):127-145.
Academic freedom: an ultra-modern principle with old roots.Li Bennich-Bjorkman - 2016 - Філософія Освіти 18 (1):125-135.
Fulfilling the Promise of Academic Freedom.Kurt Biedenkopf - 2009 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 76 (4):805-810.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-07-30

Downloads
139 (#134,216)

6 months
72 (#68,045)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Tom Vinci
Dalhousie University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The Logic of Scientific Discovery.K. Popper - 1959 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (37):55-57.
Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.Imre Lakatos - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 91-196.
The Cement of the Universe.John Earman & J. L. Mackie - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (3):390.
Causality without counterfactuals.Wesley C. Salmon - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (2):297-312.

View all 6 references / Add more references