Results for 'Analytic Geometry'

989 found
Order:
  1.  5
    The analytic geometry of genetics: part I: the structure, function, and early evolution of Punnett squares.W. C. Wimsatt - 2012 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 66 (4):359-396.
    A square tabular array was introduced by R. C. Punnett in (1907) to visualize systematically and economically the combination of gametes to make genotypes according to Mendel’s theory. This mode of representation evolved and rapidly became standardized as the canonical way of representing like problems in genetics. Its advantages over other contemporary methods are discussed, as are ways in which it evolved to increase its power and efficiency, and responded to changing theoretical perspectives. It provided a natural visual decomposition of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  21
    Synthetic and analytic geometries in the publications of Jakob Steiner and Julius Plücker.Jemma Lorenat - 2016 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 70 (4):413-462.
    In their publications during the 1820s, Jakob Steiner and Julius Plücker frequently derived the same results while claiming different methods. This paper focuses on two such results in order to compare their approaches to constructing figures, calculating with symbols, and representing geometric magnitudes. Underlying the repetitive display of similar problems and theorems, Steiner and Plücker redefined synthetic and analytic methods in distinctly personal practices.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  25
    Species richness and the analytic geometry of latitudinal and altitudinal gradients.Root Gorelick - 2008 - Acta Biotheoretica 56 (3):197-203.
    Extensive empirical work has shown that species richness decreases roughly exponentially or quadratically with latitude. What appears to be a latitudinal gradient in fact may simply be a negative correlation of latitude with area at that latitude, due to convergence of lines of meridian at the poles. There is simply less area at high latitudes, which means fewer niches and fewer opportunities for speciation, hence diminished biodiversity at high latitudes. Similarly, analytic geometry of a cone shows that species (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  11
    Is There Progress in Mathematical Discovery and Did the Greeks Have Analytic Geometry?L. C. Karpinski - 1937 - Isis 27 (1):46-52.
  5.  9
    The Basic Concepts of Mathematics. A Companion to Current Textbooks on Algebra and Analytic Geometry. Part I. Algebra.Karl Menger - 1960 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 25 (2):158-160.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  7
    Menger Karl. The basic concepts of mathematics. A companion to current textbooks on algebra and analytic geometry. Part I. Algebra. The Bookstore, Illinois Institute of Technology, Chicago 1957, vii + 93 pp. [REVIEW]Wolfgang Yourgrau - 1960 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 25 (2):158-160.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  17
    Edward W. Cogan, Robert Z. Norman, and Gerald L. Thompson. Calculus of functions of one argument. With analytic geometry and differential equations. Prentice-Hall, Inc., Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1960, x + 587 pp. [REVIEW]Edward W. Cogan, Robert Z. Norman & Gerald L. Thompson - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (4):642-642.
  8.  37
    Edward W. Cogan, Robert Z. Norman, and Gerald L. Thompson. Calculus of functions of one argument. With analytic geometry and differential equations. Prentice-Hall, Inc., Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1960, x + 587 pp. [REVIEW]William E. Gould - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (4):642-642.
  9.  25
    Review: Edward W. Cogan, Robert Z. Norman, Gerald L. Thompson, Calculus of Functions of One Argument. With Analytic Geometry and Differential Equations. [REVIEW]William E. Gould - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (4):642-642.
  10.  12
    The Analytic Art: Nine Studies in Algebra, Geometry, and Trigonometry from the Opus restitutae mathematicae analyseos, seu Algebra novaFrancois Viete T. Richard Witmer.Robin E. Rider - 1986 - Isis 77 (1):152-153.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. The Analytical Method in Descartes' Geometrie.Giorgio Israel - forthcoming - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  77
    Bridging the gap between analytic and synthetic geometry: Hilbert’s axiomatic approach.Eduardo N. Giovannini - 2016 - Synthese 193 (1):31-70.
    The paper outlines an interpretation of one of the most important and original contributions of David Hilbert’s monograph Foundations of Geometry , namely his internal arithmetization of geometry. It is claimed that Hilbert’s profound interest in the problem of the introduction of numbers into geometry responded to certain epistemological aims and methodological concerns that were fundamental to his early axiomatic investigations into the foundations of elementary geometry. In particular, it is shown that a central concern that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13. The analytic and synthetic.Hilary Putnam - 1975 - In Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge University Press. pp. 33-69.
    The present paper is an attempt to give an account of the analytic-synthetic distinction both inside and outside of physical theory. It is hoped that the paper is sufficiently nontechnical to be followed by a reader whose background in science is not extensive; but it has been necessary to consider problems connected with physical science (particularly the definition of 'kinetic energy,' and the conceptual problems connected with geometry) in order to bring out features of the analytic-synthetic distinction (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  14.  31
    Is euclidean geometry analytic?Robert French - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 49 (2):213 - 217.
  15. From geometry to phenomenology.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2008 - Synthese 162 (2):225-233.
    Richard Tieszen [Tieszen, R. (2005). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXX(1), 153–173.] has argued that the group-theoretical approach to modern geometry can be seen as a realization of Edmund Husserl’s view of eidetic intuition. In support of Tieszen’s claim, the present article discusses Husserl’s approach to geometry in 1886–1902. Husserl’s first detailed discussion of the concept of group and invariants under transformations takes place in his notes on Hilbert’s Memoir Ueber die Grundlagen der Geometrie that Hilbert wrote during the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  20
    François Viète, The Analytic Art. Nine Studies in Algebra, Geometry and Trigonometry from the ‘Opus Restitutae Mathematics Analyseos, seu Algebra Nova’. Edited by T. Richard Witmer. Kent, Ohio: State University Press [European distributor: Eurospan Ltd., 3 Henrietta Street, London WC2E] 1983. Pp. 450. ISBN 0-87338-282-X. $45. [REVIEW]D. T. Whiteside - 1985 - British Journal for the History of Science 18 (1):98-100.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  46
    Hilbert's "Foundations of Geometry".Oswald Veblen - 1903 - The Monist 13 (2):303-309.
  18. Emergence, evolution, and the geometry of logic: Causal leaps and the myth of historical development. [REVIEW]Stephen Palmquist - 2007 - Foundations of Science 12 (1):9-37.
    After sketching the historical development of “emergence” and noting several recent problems relating to “emergent properties”, this essay proposes that properties may be either “emergent” or “mergent” and either “intrinsic” or “extrinsic”. These two distinctions define four basic types of change: stagnation, permanence, flux, and evolution. To illustrate how emergence can operate in a purely logical system, the Geometry of Logic is introduced. This new method of analyzing conceptual systems involves the mapping of logical relations onto geometrical figures, following (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. Visual geometry.James Hopkins - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (1):3-34.
    We cannot imagine two straight lines intersecting at two points even though they may do so. In this case our abilities to imagine depend upon our abilities to visualise.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20. Time and physical geometry.Hilary Putnam - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (8):240-247.
  21.  6
    Geometry and analysis in Anastácio da Cunha’s calculus.João Caramalho Domingues - 2023 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 77 (6):579-600.
    It is well known that over the eighteenth century the calculus moved away from its geometric origins; Euler, and later Lagrange, aspired to transform it into a “purely analytical” discipline. In the 1780 s, the Portuguese mathematician José Anastácio da Cunha developed an original version of the calculus whose interpretation in view of that process presents challenges. Cunha was a strong admirer of Newton (who famously favoured geometry over algebra) and criticized Euler’s faith in analysis. However, the fundamental propositions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  35
    Ethics of Geometry and Genealogy of Modernity.Marc Richir - 1994 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 17 (1-2):315-324.
    The work of David R. Lachterman, The Ethics of Geometry, subtitled A Genealogy of Modernity, concerns essentially the status of geometry in Euclid’s Elements and in Descartes’s Geometry. It is a remarkable work, at once by the declared breadth of its ambitions and by the very great precision of its analyses, which are always supported by a prodigious philosophical culture. David Lachterman’s concern is to grasp, by way of an in-depth commentary of certain, particularly crucial passages of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  12
    Geometry and Chronometry in Philosophical Perspective.Lawrence Sklar & Adolf Grunbaum - 1972 - Philosophical Review 81 (4):506.
  24. Thomas Reid’s Geometry of Visibles.James Van Cleve - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):373-416.
    In a brief but remarkable section of the Inquiry into the Human Mind, Thomas Reid argued that the visual field is governed by principles other than the familiar theorems of Euclid—theorems we would nowadays classify as Riemannian. On the strength of this section, he has been credited by Norman Daniels, R. B. Angell, and others with discovering non-Euclidean geometry over half a century before the mathematicians—sixty years before Lobachevsky and ninety years before Riemann. I believe that Reid does indeed (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  25.  45
    World Geometry.V. F. Lenzen - 1931 - The Monist 41 (4):481-511.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  38
    Geometry and necessary truth.Raymond D. Bradley - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (1):59-75.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  19
    Thomas Reid’s Geometry of Visibles.James Van Cleve - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):373-416.
    In a brief but remarkable section of the Inquiry into the Human Mind, Thomas Reid argued that the visual field is governed by principles other than the familiar theorems of Euclid—theorems we would nowadays classify as Riemannian. On the strength of this section, he has been credited by Norman Daniels, R. B. Angell, and others with discovering non-Euclidean geometry over half a century before the mathematicians—sixty years before Lobachevsky and ninety years before Riemann. I believe that Reid does indeed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  28. ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC AND EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY.John Corcoran - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):131-2.
    John Corcoran and George Boger. Aristotelian logic and Euclidean geometry. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 20 (2014) 131. -/- By an Aristotelian logic we mean any system of direct and indirect deductions, chains of reasoning linking conclusions to premises—complete syllogisms, to use Aristotle’s phrase—1) intended to show that their conclusions follow logically from their respective premises and 2) resembling those in Aristotle’s Prior Analytics. Such systems presuppose existence of cases where it is not obvious that the conclusion follows from the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  62
    Frege’s philosophy of geometry.Matthias Schirn - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):929-971.
    In this paper, I critically discuss Frege’s philosophy of geometry with special emphasis on his position in The Foundations of Arithmetic of 1884. In Sect. 2, I argue that that what Frege calls faculty of intuition in his dissertation is probably meant to refer to a capacity of visualizing geometrical configurations structurally in a way which is essentially the same for most Western educated human beings. I further suggest that according to his Habilitationsschrift it is through spatial intuition that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30. Kant's theory of geometry.Michael Friedman - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (4):455-506.
  31. On the Foundations of Geometry.Henri Poincaré - 1898 - The Monist 9 (1):1-43.
  32. How euclidean geometry has misled metaphysics.Graham Nerlich - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):169-189.
  33.  15
    How Euclidean Geometry Has Misled Metaphysics.Graham Nerlich - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):169-189.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  34.  11
    Hume’s View of Geometry.Ruth Weintraub - 2023 - In Carl Posy & Yemima Ben-Menahem (eds.), Mathematical Knowledge, Objects and Applications: Essays in Memory of Mark Steiner. Springer. pp. 329-343.
    I start by considering Mark Steiner’s startling claim that Hume takes geometry to be synthetic a priori, which engenders the Kantian challenge to explain how such knowledge is possible. I argue, in response, that Steiner misinterprets the (deceptive) relevant passage from Hume, and that Hume, as the received view has it, takes geometry to be analytic, although in a more expansive sense of the word than the modern one. I then note a new challenge geometry engenders (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  86
    On the Foundations of Geometry.Gottlob Frege - 1960 - Philosophical Review 69 (1):3-17.
  36.  89
    Space and Geometry from the Point of View of Physical Inquiry.Ernst Mach - 1903 - The Monist 14 (1):1-32.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  37. Ernst Cassirer's Neo-Kantian Philosophy of Geometry.Jeremy Heis - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (4):759 - 794.
    One of the most important philosophical topics in the early twentieth century and a topic that was seminal in the emergence of analytic philosophy was the relationship between Kantian philosophy and modern geometry. This paper discusses how this question was tackled by the Neo-Kantian trained philosopher Ernst Cassirer. Surprisingly, Cassirer does not affirm the theses that contemporary philosophers often associate with Kantian philosophy of mathematics. He does not defend the necessary truth of Euclidean geometry but instead develops (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  38.  29
    Analytical symbols and geometrical figures in eighteenth-century calculus.Giovanni Ferraro - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 32 (3):535-555.
    Leibnizian-Newtonian calculus was a theory that dealt with geometrical objects; the figure continued to play one of the fundamental roles it had played in Greek geometry: it susbstituted a part of reasoning. During the eighteenth century a process of de-geometrization of calculus took place, which consisted in the rejection of the use of diagrams and in considering calculus as an 'intellectual' system where deduction was merely linguistic and mediated. This was achieved by interpreting variables as universal quantities and introducing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39. After Non-Euclidean Geometry: Intuition, Truth and the Autonomy of Mathematics.Janet Folina - 2018 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (3).
    The mathematical developments of the 19th century seemed to undermine Kant’s philosophy. Non-Euclidean geometries challenged Kant’s view that there is a spatial intuition rich enough to yield the truth of Euclidean geometry. Similarly, advancements in algebra challenged the view that temporal intuition provides a foundation for both it and arithmetic. Mathematics seemed increasingly detached from experience as well as its form; moreover, with advances in symbolic logic, mathematical inference also seemed independent of intuition. This paper considers various philosophical responses (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Toward a topic-specific logicism? Russell's theory of geometry in the principles of mathematics.Sébastien Gandon - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (1):35-72.
    Russell's philosophy is rightly described as a programme of reduction of mathematics to logic. Now the theory of geometry developed in 1903 does not fit this picture well, since it is deeply rooted in the purely synthetic projective approach, which conflicts with all the endeavours to reduce geometry to analytical geometry. The first goal of this paper is to present an overview of this conception. The second aim is more far-reaching. The fact that such a theory of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41. Kant's Philosophy of Geometry.William Mark Goodwin - 2003 - Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley
    In my dissertation, I argue that contemporary interpretive work on Kant's philosophy of geometry has failed to understand properly the diagrammatic aspects of Euclidean reasoning. Attention to these aspects is amply repaid, not only because it provides substantial insight into the role of intuition in Kant's philosophy of mathematics, but also because it brings out both the force and the limitations of Kant's philosophical account of geometry. ;Kant characterizes the predecessors with which he was engaged as agreeing that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  14
    The Geometry of Vision and the Mind Body Problem. [REVIEW]David Hilbert & Robert E. French - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (2):293.
  43.  16
    The Geometry of Art and Life. [REVIEW]R. M. Ogden - 1947 - Philosophical Review 56 (4):456-456.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  10
    The Geometry of Vision and the Mind Body Problem. [REVIEW]David Hilbert - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (2):293-297.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  76
    Introduction to Geometry[REVIEW]Howard Levi - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (1):19-21.
  46.  10
    The Non-Euclidean Geometry Inevitable.George Bruce Halsted - 1894 - The Monist 4 (4):483-493.
  47.  39
    The Non-Euclidean Geometry Inevitable.George Bruce Halsted - 1894 - The Monist 4 (4):483-493.
  48. Non-euclidean geometry and the Kantian a priori.F. C. S. Schiller - 1896 - Philosophical Review 5 (2):173-180.
  49.  76
    The Foundations of Geometry.Paul Carus - 1903 - The Monist 13 (3):370-397.
  50.  7
    The Foundations of Geometry (concluded).Paul Carus - 1903 - The Monist 13 (4):493-522.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 989