Pseudosentences, Auto-Misunderstanding, and Formalization

In Michael Nathan Goldberg, Andreas Mauz & Christiane Tietz (eds.), Missverstehen -- Zu einer Urszene der Hermeneutik. Brill | Schöningh. pp. 45-69 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In the early Analytic Philosophy, the concept of a pseudosentence was used as a polemical device. To try and formalize a sentence without success was a means to ›debunk‹ it as a pseudosentence. The classical example is Heidegger’s dictum of the nothing which noths. But, according to Carnap, not only did Carnap not understand what Heidegger said, but also Heidegger himself must have misunderstood his own utterances! Does Carnap's diagnosis remain intact if one admits the possibility of a misunderstanding and misconstrual on Carnap’s side, too? Should not Carnap's concept of formalization be substituted by that of logico-hermeneutical reconstruction in order to obviate any such infelicities? In everyday communication, we very rarely ever feel the need to undertake a significant effort to understand each other. This attitude is at odds with Friedrich Schleiermacher’s view that misunderstandings are ubiquitous and that one has to actively invest into the establishment of correct understandings. Therefore, one should ask: Are there good reasons to reject the view that we misunderstand ourselves all the time? Or: Is there any worth in the view that misunderstandings are prevalent? The answers developed in this paper are generalized so that they apply to philosophical contexts and a maxim of escalating formalization is formulated. The debate about peer disagreement is adduced as an illustration of philosophical practices that evade the maxim and thus stagnate cognitively.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 92,197

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Dialectic of Formalization.Magdalena Germek - 2021 - Filozofski Vestnik 42 (1).
Limitations of formalization.Constantine Politis - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3/4):356-360.
On The Logical Formalization of Ansem's Ontological Argument.Ricardo Silvestre - 2015 - Revista Brasileira de Filosofia da Religião 2 (1):142–161.
Analysis of (')Pseudoproblems(').Moritz Cordes - 2019 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 22 (1):137-159.
The Philosophical Achievement of Jacob Klein.Burt Hopkins - 2011 - New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 11:282-296.
Derrida.Charles Ramond - 2007 - Cités 30 (2):143-.
The Philosophical Achievement of Jacob Klein.Burt Hopkins - 2011 - New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 11:282-296.
From Time to Time: Auto-Affection in Derrida’s 1964-65 Heidegger Course.Tracy Colony - 2019 - Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 27 (1):14-33.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-02-22

Downloads
35 (#458,712)

6 months
17 (#151,142)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Moritz Cordes
Center for Advanced Internet Studies Bochum

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Foundations of Illocutionary Logic.John Rogers Searle & Daniel Vanderveken - 1985 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
The logical structure of the world.Rudolf Carnap - 1967 - Chicago and La Salle, Ill.: Open Court. Edited by Rudolf Carnap.
Disagreement.Jonathan Matheson & Bryan Frances - 2018 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

View all 26 references / Add more references