Towards a Value-Neutral Definition of Sport

Sport, Ethics and Philosophy:1-16 (2023)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In this paper I argue that philosophers of sport should avoid value-laden definitions of sport; that is, they should avoid building into the definition of sport that they are inherently worthwhile activities. Sports may very well often be worthwhile as a contingent matter, but this should not be taken to be a core feature included in the definition of sport. I start by outlining what I call the ‘legitimacy-conferring’ element of the category ‘sport’. I then argue that we ought not to include such a dimension in our definition of sport, on the grounds that it confuses issues of description with issues of definition: the issue of what sport does with what sport is. Following this, I consider a Wittgensteinian family resemblance approach to defining sport; Kevin Schieman’s argument that sports are necessarily good games; and the oft-cited wide-following and institutional criteria, as arguments for including an evaluative dimension in the definition of sport. I conclude that none succeed, for similar reasons: they either fail to track our common sense intuitions about what does or does not count as a sport; and/or they make it impossible for us to ever describe something a ‘bad’ sport (or instance of sport). Just as a good definition of, say, art, shouldn’t make it impossible for us to describe something as ‘bad art’, I argue that our definition of sport shouldn’t build in a necessarily positive evaluation. I conclude by discussing some of the practical reasons why supporters of activities about which there is currently debate as to their status as sports might want to see those activities included under the sports umbrella, but suggest that this on its own isn’t a good reason for modifying a philosophical definition of sport to include them.

Similar books and articles

On the Definition of Sport.Jim Parry - 2022 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 17 (1):49-57.
Martin in the field.Lev Kreft - 2008 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 2 (1):71 – 83.
Conventionalism Revisited.Bogdan Ciomaga - 2012 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 6 (4):410-422.
Sport for the Sake of the Soul.Michael W. Austin - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 12 (1):20-29.
Sport Realism: A Law-Inspired Theory of Sport.Aaron Harper - 2022 - Lanham, MD, USA: Lexington Books.
Philosophy and Sport: Volume 73.Anthony O'Hear (ed.) - 2013 - Cambridge University Press.
Philosophy and Sport.Anthony O'Hear (ed.) - 2013 - Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
Enhancement in Sport, and Enhancement outside Sport.Thomas Douglas - 2007 - Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 1 (1).
E-sports are Not Sports.Jim Parry - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (1):3-18.
Introduction to the Philosophy of Sport.Heather Lynne Reid - 2012 - Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Reverse Play: Toward A Philosophy From Sport.Albert Piacente - 2015 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (1):58-74.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-09-30

Downloads
349 (#58,596)

6 months
256 (#9,361)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Michael Hemmingsen
Tunghai University

Citations of this work

Mapping the terrain of sport: a core-periphery model.Michael Hemmingsen - 2024 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport (1):1-23.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Mapping the terrain of sport: a core-periphery model.Michael Hemmingsen - 2024 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport (1):1-23.
The Elements of Sport.Bernard Suits - 2007 - In William John Morgan (ed.), Ethics in Sport. Human Kinetics. pp. 9--19.
E-sports are Not Sports.Jim Parry - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (1):3-18.
Movement compression, sports and eSports.Michael Hemmingsen - 2023 - European Journal for Sport and Society:1-19.
Triad Trickery: Playing With Sport and Games.Klaus V. Meier - 1988 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 15 (1):11-30.

View all 19 references / Add more references