26 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Benjamin E. Berkman [21]Benjamin Berkman [4]Ben Berkman [1]
  1.  40
    Implementing Expanded Prenatal Genetic Testing: Should Parents Have Access to Any and All Fetal Genetic Information?Michelle J. Bayefsky & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2022 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (2):4-22.
    Prenatal genetic testing is becoming available for an increasingly broad set of diseases, and it is only a matter of time before parents can choose to test for hundreds, if not thousands, of genetic conditions in their fetuses. Should access to certain kinds of fetal genetic information be limited, and if so, on what basis? We evaluate a range of considerations including reproductive autonomy, parental rights, disability rights, and the rights and interests of the fetus as a potential future child. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  2.  78
    Broad Consent for Research With Biological Samples: Workshop Conclusions.Christine Grady, Lisa Eckstein, Ben Berkman, Dan Brock, Robert Cook-Deegan, Stephanie M. Fullerton, Hank Greely, Mats G. Hansson, Sara Hull, Scott Kim, Bernie Lo, Rebecca Pentz, Laura Rodriguez, Carol Weil, Benjamin S. Wilfond & David Wendler - 2015 - American Journal of Bioethics 15 (9):34-42.
    Different types of consent are used to obtain human biospecimens for future research. This variation has resulted in confusion regarding what research is permitted, inadvertent constraints on future research, and research proceeding without consent. The National Institutes of Health Clinical Center's Department of Bioethics held a workshop to consider the ethical acceptability of addressing these concerns by using broad consent for future research on stored biospecimens. Multiple bioethics scholars, who have written on these issues, discussed the reasons for consent, the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  3.  31
    A New Ethical Framework for Assessing the Unique Challenges of Fetal Therapy Trials: Response to Commentaries.Saskia Hendriks, Christine Grady, David Wasserman, David Wendler, Diana W. Bianchi & Benjamin Berkman - 2022 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (3):45-61.
    New fetal therapies offer important prospects for improving health. However, having to consider both the fetus and the pregnant woman makes the risk–benefit analysis of fetal therapy trials challenging. Regulatory guidance is limited, and proposed ethical frameworks are overly restrictive or permissive. We propose a new ethical framework for fetal therapy research. First, we argue that considering only biomedical benefits fails to capture all relevant interests. Thus, we endorse expanding the considered benefits to include evidence-based psychosocial effects of fetal therapies. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4.  45
    Do Researchers Have an Obligation to Actively Look for Genetic Incidental Findings?Catherine Gliwa & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (2):32-42.
    The rapid growth of next-generation genetic sequencing has prompted debate about the responsibilities of researchers toward genetic incidental findings. Assuming there is a duty to disclose significant incidental findings, might there be an obligation for researchers to actively look for these findings? We present an ethical framework for analyzing whether there is a positive duty to look for genetic incidental findings. Using the ancillary care framework as a guide, we identify three main criteria that must be present to give rise (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  5.  21
    The Ethics of Allocating Uterine Transplants.Michelle J. Bayefsky & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2016 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (3):350-365.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  6.  49
    Genomic Inheritances: Disclosing Individual Research Results From Whole-Exome Sequencing to Deceased Participants' Relatives.Ben Chan, Flavia M. Facio, Haley Eidem, Sara Chandros Hull, Leslie G. Biesecker & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2012 - American Journal of Bioethics 12 (10):1-8.
    Whole-genome analysis and whole-exome analysis generate many more clinically actionable findings than traditional targeted genetic analysis. These findings may be relevant to research participants themselves as well as for members of their families. Though researchers performing genomic analyses are likely to find medically significant genetic variations for nearly every research participant, what they will find for any given participant is unpredictable. The ubiquity and diversity of these findings complicate questions about disclosing individual genetic test results. We outline an approach for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  7.  35
    A Framework for Analyzing the Ethics of Disclosing Genetic Research Findings.Lisa Eckstein, Jeremy R. Garrett & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (2):190-207.
    Over the past decade, there has been an extensive debate about whether researchers have an obligation to disclose genetic research findings, including primary and secondary findings. There appears to be an emerging (but disputed) view that researchers have some obligation to disclose some genetic findings to some research participants. The contours of this obligation, however, remain unclear. -/- As this paper will explore, much of this confusion is definitional or conceptual in nature. The extent of a researcher’s obligation to return (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  8.  32
    Prenatal Whole Genome Sequencing.Greer Donley, Sara Chandros Hull & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2012 - Hastings Center Report 42 (4):28-40.
    Whole genome sequencing is quickly becoming more affordable and accessible, with the prospect of personal genome sequencing for under $1,000 now widely said to be in sight. The ethical issues raised by the use of this technology in the research context have received some significant attention, but little has been written on its use in the clinical context, and most of this analysis has been futuristic forecasting. This is problematic, given the speed with which whole genome sequencing technology is likely (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  9.  69
    What Does the Duty to Warn Require?Seema K. Shah, Sara Chandros Hull, Michael A. Spinner, Benjamin E. Berkman, Lauren A. Sanchez, Ruquyyah Abdul-Karim, Amy P. Hsu, Reginald Claypool & Steven M. Holland - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (10):62 - 63.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10.  37
    The “Right Not to Know” in the Genomic Era: Time to Break From Tradition?Benjamin E. Berkman & Sara Chandros Hull - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (3):28-31.
  11.  12
    Re-examining the Ethics of Genetic Counselling in the Genomic Era.Will Schupmann, Leila Jamal & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2020 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 17 (3):325-335.
    Respect for patient autonomy has served as the dominant ethical principle of genetic counselling, but as we move into a genomic era, it is time to actively re-examine the role that this principle plays in genetic counselling practice. In this paper, we argue that the field of genetic counselling should move away from its emphasis on patient autonomy and toward the incorporation of a more balanced set of principles that allows counsellors to offer clear guidance about how best to obtain (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12. When Should Genome Researchers Disclose Misattributed Pahentage?Amulya Mandava, Joseph Millum & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2015 - Hastings Center Report 45 (4):28-36.
    Research studies increasingly use genomic sequencing to draw inferences based on comparisons between the genetic data of a set of purportedly related individuals. As use of this method progresses, it will become much more common to discover that the assumed biological relationships between the individuals are mistaken. Consequently, researchers will have to grapple with decisions about whether to return incidental findings of misattributed parentage on a much larger scale than ever before. In this paper we provide an extended argument for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  30
    Scrutinizing the Right Not to Know.Benjamin E. Berkman, Sara Chandros Hull & Leslie G. Biesecker - 2015 - American Journal of Bioethics 15 (7):17-19.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  19
    Commentary on ‘The right not to know and the obligation not to know’.Benjamin Berkman - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (5):304-305.
    The idea of a right not to know emerged in the late 20th century, largely in response to the early incorporation of genetic testing into clinical care. While a few commentators took a more absolute view about the strength of the RNTK, most of the scholarship was openly sceptical of the concept, or at least was willing to acknowledge that the RNTK was defeasible.1 After two decades of relative quiet, it was surprising, then, that the RNTK reappeared with a seemingly (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  7
    When Does an Illness Begin: Genetic Discrimination and Disease Manifestation.Anya E. R. Prince & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):655-664.
    The Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act of 2008 was passed to encourage patients to seek genetic testing that could improve health outcomes and provide opportunities for preventive measures. GINA protects individuals from discrimination based upon genetic information, but not upon manifested diseases and conditions. Because the manifestation of a disease establishes a threshold of protection for individuals under GINA, the definition of manifestation is crucial to understanding the scope of the bill. This paper examines the range of possible legal definitions of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  19
    When Does an Illness Begin: Genetic Discrimination and Disease Manifestation.Anya E. R. Prince & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):655-664.
    Congress passed the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act of 2008 in order to remove a perceived barrier to clinical genetic testing. By banning health insurance companies and employers from discriminating against an individual based on his or her genetic information, legislators hoped that patients would be encouraged to seek genetic testing that could improve health outcomes and provide opportunities for preventive measures. Their explicit legislative goal was to fully protect the public from discrimination and allay their concerns about the potential for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. Allocation of scarce biospecimens for use in research.Leah Pierson, Sophia Gibert, Benjamin Berkman, Marion Danis & Joseph Millum - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (11):740-743.
    Hundreds of millions of rare biospecimens are stored in laboratories and biobanks around the world. Often, the researchers who possess these specimens do not plan to use them, while other researchers limit the scope of their work because they cannot acquire biospecimens that meet their needs. This situation raises an important and underexplored question: how should scientists allocate biospecimens that they do not intend to use? We argue that allocators should aim to maximise the social value of the research enterprise (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  20
    When to Disclose a Borderline Incidental Finding.Benjamin E. Berkman & Susanna McGrew - 2022 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (10):91-93.
    There can be some direct clinical value to receiving valid incidental findings of XXY for most individuals with Klinefelter’s syndrome. The severity of Klinefelter’s and the magnitude of benefit fr...
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  40
    Teaching Health Law: Teaching Law Students to Be Policymakers: The Health and Science Policy Workshop on Genomic Research.Benjamin E. Berkman & Karen H. Rothenberg - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (1):147-153.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  18
    A New Ethical Framework for Assessing the Unique Challenges of Fetal Therapy Trials: Response to Commentaries.Benjamin E. Berkman, Diana W. Bianchi, David Wendler, David Wasserman, Christine Grady & Saskia Hendriks - 2022 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (3):W1-W3.
    New fetal therapies offer important prospects for improving health. However, having to consider both the fetus and the pregnant woman makes the risk–benefit analysis of fetal therapy trials challenging. Regulatory guidance is limited, and proposed ethical frameworks are overly restrictive or permissive. We propose a new ethical framework for fetal therapy research. First, we argue that considering only biomedical benefits fails to capture all relevant interests. Thus, we endorse expanding the considered benefits to include evidence-based psychosocial effects of fetal therapies. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  13
    Should Patient Groups Have the Power to Redirect How Their Samples Are Used?Eleanor T. Chung & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (8):26-28.
    The authors of the target article briefly discuss the issue of “sample ownership” when scientists collaborate with citizen science partners (Wiggins and Wilbanks 2019). This is an important issue,...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  11
    Should institutions fund the feedback of individual findings in genomic research?Cornelius Ewuoso, Benjamin Berkman, Ambroise Wonkam & Jantina de Vries - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Ethics.
    The article argues the thesis that institutions have a prima facie obligation to fund the feedback of individual findings in genomic research conducted on the African continent by drawing arguments from an underexplored Afro-communitarian view of distributive justice and rights of researchers to be aided. Whilst some studies have explored how institutions have a duty to support return as a form of ancillary care or additional foreseeable service in research by mostly appealing to dominant principles and theories in the Global (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  18
    Response to Open Peer Commentaries on “Do Researchers Have an Obligation to Actively Look for Genetic Incidental Findings?”.Catherine Gliwa & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5):W10-W11.
  24.  42
    Response to Open Peer Commentaries on “Genomic Inheritances: Disclosing Individual Research Results From Whole-Exome Sequencing to Deceased Participants' Relatives”.Sara Chandros Hull, Ben Chan, Leslie G. Biesecker & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2012 - American Journal of Bioethics 12 (12):W9-W10.
  25.  14
    Development of a consensus approach for return of pathology incidental findings in the Genotype-Tissue Expression (GTEx) project.Nicole C. Lockhart, Carol J. Weil, Latarsha J. Carithers, Susan E. Koester, A. Roger Little, Simona Volpi, Helen M. Moore & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (9):643-645.
    The active debate about the return of incidental or secondary findings in research has primarily focused on return to research participants, or in some cases, family members. Particular attention has been paid to return of genomic findings. Yet, research may generate other types of findings that warrant consideration for return, including findings related to the pathology of donated biospecimens. In the case of deceased biospecimen donors who are also organ and/or tissue transplant donors, pathology incidental findings may be relevant not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  16
    Autonomy concerns with using contracts to enhance patient adherence.Camila Losada Strassle, Ben Schwan & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2022 - Bioethics 36 (6):666-672.
    The failure of many patients with chronic conditions to correctly follow medical advice that they hope or intend to follow is a major concern, especially as effective long‐term therapies for chronic conditions materialize. Some US healthcare providers have responded with strategies that involve implementing contracts with their patients, including provisions that may deny future treatments after continued nonadherence. This is among the first articles to explicitly discuss the ethics of patient contracts.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark