7 found
Order:
  1.  30
    The Nash solution is more utilitarian than egalitarian.Shiran Rachmilevitch - 2015 - Theory and Decision 79 (3):463-478.
    I state and prove formal versions of the claim that the Nash bargaining solution creates a compromise between egalitarianism and utilitarianism, but that this compromise is “biased”: the Nash solution puts more emphasis on utilitarianism than it puts on egalitarianism. I also extend the bargaining model by assuming that utility can be transferred between the players at some cost ; I use the extended model to better understand the connections between egalitarianism and utilitarianism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  53
    Egalitarian–utilitarian bounds in Nash’s bargaining problem.Shiran Rachmilevitch - 2016 - Theory and Decision 80 (3):427-442.
    For every 2-person bargaining problem, the Nash bargaining solution selects a point that is “between” the relative utilitarian point and the relative egalitarian point. Also, it is “between” the utilitarian and egalitarian points. I improve these bounds. I also derive a new characterization of the Nash solution which combines a bounds property together with strong individual rationality and an axiom which is new to Nash’s bargaining model, the sandwich axiom. The sandwich axiom is a weakening of Nash’s IIA.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  27
    Implementing egalitarianism in a class of Nash demand games.Emin Karagözoğlu & Shiran Rachmilevitch - 2018 - Theory and Decision 85 (3-4):495-508.
    We add a stage to Nash’s demand game by allowing the greedier player to revise his demand if the demands are not jointly feasible. If he decides to stick to his initial demand, then the game ends and no one receives anything. If he decides to revise it down to 1-x\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$1-x$$\end{document}, where x is his initial demand, the revised demand is implemented with certainty. The implementation probability changes linearly between these two (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  11
    The Nash bargaining solution: sometimes more utilitarian, sometimes more egalitarian.Shiran Rachmilevitch - 2023 - Theory and Decision 95 (3):457-464.
    The first-order condition of the Nash bargaining solution equates the ratio of utilities to the ratio of marginal utilities. It turns out that this common ratio plays a role in determining whether the Nash solution, roughly speaking, is “more utilitarian” or “more egalitarian.” More specifically, I propose a sense of proximity to utilitarianism and/or egalitarianism according to which, in bargaining problems with distinct utilitarian and egalitarian points, the Nash solution is closer to utilitarianism if the aforementioned ratio is smaller than (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  14
    Folk theorems in a bargaining game with endogenous protocol.Shiran Rachmilevitch - 2019 - Theory and Decision 86 (3-4):389-399.
    Two players bargain to select a utility allocation in some set X⊂R+2\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$X\subset {\mathbb {R}}_+^2$$\end{document}. Bargaining takes place in infinite discrete time, where each period t is divided into two sub-periods. In the first sub-period, the players play a simultaneous-move game to determine that period’s proposer, and bargaining takes place in the second sub-period. Rejection triggers a one-period delay and move to t+1\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$t+1$$\end{document}. For (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  87
    Randomized dictatorship and the Kalai–Smorodinsky bargaining solution.Shiran Rachmilevitch - 2014 - Theory and Decision 76 (2):173-177.
    “Randomized dictatorship,” one of the simplest ways to solve bargaining situations, works as follows: a fair coin toss determines the “dictator”—the player to be given his first-best payoff. The two major bargaining solutions, that of Nash and that of Kalai and Smorodinsky, Pareto-dominate this process. However, whereas the existing literature offers axiomatizations of the Nash solution in which this ex ante domination plays a central role, it does not provide an analogous result for Kalai–Smorodinsky. This paper fills in this gap: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Reasonable Nash demand games.Shiran Rachmilevitch - 2021 - Theory and Decision 93 (2):319-330.
    In the Nash demand game n players announce utility demands, the demands are implemented if they are jointly feasible, and otherwise no one gets anything. If the utilities set is the simplex, the game is called “divide-the-dollar”. Brams and Taylor studied variants of divide-the-dollar, on which they imposed reasonableness conditions. I explore the implications of these conditions on general NDGs. In any reasonable NDG, the egalitarian demand profile cannot be obtained via iterated elimination of weakly dominated strategies. Further, a reasonable (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark